Bültmann & Gerriets
Opting for the Best
Oughts and Options
von Douglas W Portmore
Verlag: Oxford University Press
Reihe: Oxford Moral Theory
Gebundene Ausgabe
ISBN: 978-0-19-094535-0
Erschienen am 10.07.2019
Sprache: Englisch
Format: 241 mm [H] x 169 mm [B] x 35 mm [T]
Gewicht: 612 Gramm
Umfang: 346 Seiten

Preis: 117,50 €
keine Versandkosten (Inland)


Jetzt bestellen und voraussichtlich ab dem 24. Oktober in der Buchhandlung abholen.

Der Versand innerhalb der Stadt erfolgt in Regel am gleichen Tag.
Der Versand nach außerhalb dauert mit Post/DHL meistens 1-2 Tage.

klimaneutral
Der Verlag produziert nach eigener Angabe noch nicht klimaneutral bzw. kompensiert die CO2-Emissionen aus der Produktion nicht. Daher übernehmen wir diese Kompensation durch finanzielle Förderung entsprechender Projekte. Mehr Details finden Sie in unserer Klimabilanz.
Klappentext
Inhaltsverzeichnis
Biografische Anmerkung

When making decisions, we ought to choose the option that is best in terms of what ultimately matters. However, knowing what ultimately matters is not always enough when it comes to knowing what we ought to do. In Opting for the Best, Douglas Portmore examines the questions that remain after we have determined what matters. In doing so, he engages with some of the most complex puzzles concerning what we ought to do, including those involving supererogation,indeterminate or overdetermined outcomes, predictable future misbehavior, among others.



  • Preface

  • Acknowledgements

  • 1. Opting for the Best

  • 1.1 The Opting-for-the-Best View

  • 1.1.1. Perhaps, some options that ought to be performed are suboptimal

  • 1.1.2. Not all possible events are eligible for deontic status

  • 1.1.3. Alternatives matter

  • 1.1.4. Oughts versus obligations

  • 1.1.5. Best option versus best outcome

  • 1.1.6. The best must be sufficiently good

  • 1.1.7. 'Option' versus 'can'

  • 1.1.8. Objective oughts versus subjective oughts

  • 1.1.9. Directive oughts versus evaluative oughts

  • 1.2 The Ecumenical Nature of the View

  • 1.3 A Potential Objection to the Opting-for-the-Best View

  • 1.4 Remaining Controversies and the Plan for the Rest of the Book

  • 2. What are our options?

  • 2.1 The Need to Restrict What Can Count as an Option

  • 2.2 The Necessity of Control

  • 2.3 The Sufficiency of Control

  • 2.4 Conclusion

  • 3. What's the relevant sort of control?

  • 3.1 Complete and Synchronic Control

  • 3.2 Personal Control versus Sub-Personal Control

  • 3.3 Rational Control versus Volitional Control

  • 3.3.1. Formations of attitudes

  • 3.3.2. Mixed acts

  • 3.3.3. Automatic, unthinking acts

  • 3.3.4. Acts stemming from volitions that weren't under the subject's rational control

  • 3.3.5. Acts that manifested a poor quality of will and were expressive of one's deep self but were not under one's rational control

  • 3.3.6. Lapses

  • 3.4 Volitional Control and the Trouble with Insisting on Always Tracing Back to Some Intentional Act

  • 3.5 What about voluntary control?

  • 3.6 Conclusion

  • 4. Which options have their deontic statuses in virtue of their own goodness?

  • 4.1 Omnism (All Options) and the Problem of Act Versions

  • 4.2 Nonnullusism (Only Some Options)

  • 4.3 Nullusism (No Option)

  • 4.4 Supererogation and the Latitude Problem

  • 4.5 Supererogation and Evaluative Inheritance

  • 4.6 Three Objections to Maximalism

  • 4.6.1. Ross's Paradox

  • 4.6.2. The Arbitrariness Objection

  • 4.6.3. The Implausible Grounds Objection

  • 4.7 The Implications of Maximalism

  • 5. Rationalist Maximalism

  • 5.1 Three More Objections to Maximalism

  • 5.1.1. The 'Did ?'-Implies-'Had the option to ?' Objection

  • 5.1.2. Gustafsson's Objection

  • 5.1.3. The Professor Procrastinate Objection

  • 5.2 The Actualism/Possibilism Distinction versus the Omnism/Maximalism Distinction

  • 5.3 The Principle of Moral Harmony and the Problem of Overdetermination

  • 5.4 Conclusion

  • 6. Maximalism and the Ought-Most-Reason View

  • 6.1 Omnism and Maximalism about Reasons

  • 6.2 The Inheritance Problem for Omnism

  • 6.3 The Intuition Problem for Omnism

  • 6.4 The All or Nothing Problem for Omnism

  • 6.5 Maximalism and the Basic Belief

  • 6.6 Objections to Maximalism about Reasons

  • 6.6.1. Incorrect Explanation

  • 6.6.2. Incorrect Weights

  • 6.6.3. Incorrect Account of Instrumental Reasons

  • 6.6.4. Incorrect Account of Reasons to Perform Acts with Side Effects

  • 6.7 Conclusion

  • 7. Which, if either, are we to assess directly in terms of what ultimately matters: our options or their prospects?

  • 7.1 A Case Study: Teleology, Deontology, Non-Teleology, and Agent-Centered Constraints

  • 7.2 Ignorance versus Indeterminacy

  • 7.3 Indeterminacy and Subjective Rightness

  • 7.4 Indeterminacy and Objective Rightness

  • 7.5 A Teleological Approach

  • 7.6 Rationalist Teleological Maximalism

  • 8. Rationalist Teleological Maximalism

  • 8.1 An Illustration of How Rationalist Teleological Maximalism Works

  • 8.2 Rationalist Teleological Maximalism's Many Virtues

  • 8.3 On What Matters and the Importance of Structure

  • Glossary

  • Bibliography

  • Index



Douglas W. Portmore is Professor of Philosophy in the School of Historical, Philosophical, and Religious Studies at Arizona State University. He is the author of Commonsense Consequentialism: Wherein Morality Meets Rationality (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011) and is an Associate Editor for Ethics: An International Journal of Social, Political and Legal Philosophy. His research focuses mainly on morality, rationality, and the interconnections between the two, but he has also written on well-being, posthumous harm, and the non-identity problem.


andere Formate
weitere Titel der Reihe